no publication statement available
Written by OpenOffice
The present volume, which constitutes the proceedings of the eponymous conference held in May 2019 at the Polish Institute in
Berlin, offers a striking insight into the profoundly networked forms and practices of Neo-Kantian philosophy. Adopting an
original perspective on the movement, the materials gathered here firmly
establish that the scope and impact of Neo-Kantianism in the landscape of
European culture and ideas can only be properly understood if one takes into
account not just its main German “schools” (Marburg, Baden) but also its
inter-disciplinary and cross-cultural dissemination in other intellectual
contexts, not least in Poland and Russia.th century and the slow rise of “new”
human sciences or Geisteswissenschaften (anthropology,
art theory, cultural studies, linguistics, literary theory, sociology, etc.)
around 1900.
On a more cautious note, it is worth underlining that the present volume does not
purport to offer a systematic defence of these two
arguments regarding both the networked nature of Neo-Kantian philosophy and its
pivotal role in the reconfiguration of science and knowledge at the turn of the
20th century. Notwithstanding a score of interesting
elements on the specific topics highlighted by each paper, the present volume
provides rather a first outline, a) establishing what one could call the “frame
of relevance” of Neo-Kantian philosophy and b) underlining the importance of
analysing it specifically in terms of a multilateral, multipolar network. Most
of the work towards contextualising and reassessing the networked role of
Neo-Kantianism in the European history of ideas remains to be done. As such,
this volume can be considered as a first step in the exploration and
demonstration of a general hypothesis.
That hypothesis itself, however, is the result of a protracted and already mature reflection, which was progressively initiated in Tübingen and Moscow in 2013 thanks to multiple discussions between the editors over the status of Neo-Kantian philosophy and, specifically, its role in the development of “Russian Theory” (cf. Zenkin 2004).
The starting point of our discussions, and the basis of our future hypothesis on
the pivotal European role of Neo-Kantianism was a strange discrepancy we noticed
in the common treatment of the German sources of Russian Formalism. On the one
hand, we found a wide recognition and very detailed studies of the Formalists’
psychological sources (cf. SDmitriev 2002, vetlikova
2005, Tchougounnikov & Romand 2009), and indeed of their inspiration in
German philology (Humboldt, Goethe) or formalist art history (Wöllflin) or even aesthetics (Hanslick,
Worringer). On the other hand, their debt to German philosophy has often been
acknowledged only very summarily and dismissed as being of at most secondary
interest given the Russian Formalists’ own distrust of philosophy as a
discipline (cf. Hansen-Löve 1978 on the reception of phenomenology, Depretto
2009 on the Formalists’ philosophical background). Neo-Kantianism itself was
often mentioned as belonging to the Zeitgeist (Erlich
1955), and thus constituting a sort of philosophical background to Russian
Formalism, but its specific impact was not analysed by any of the leading
specialists whether within or outside Russia.
Speculating on the possible causes of this somewhat ambivalent neglect (as mentioned, the spectral presence of Neo-Kantianism as a philosophical backdrop to Russian Formalism is widely recognised), we noticed that the recognition of the impact of Neo-Kantian philosophy beyond the bounds of German academic philosophy (and even within these bounds) has tended to be very limited. Many of the direct successors to Neo-Kantian philosophy, whether its most obvious (phenomenology) or most antagonistic (logical positivism, critical theory), tended to neuter its importance and to function more as replacements, that then cast their long shadow over it. Thus, to take a few examples, the extent of Husserl’s debt to Natorp is usually papered over, and the same applies to Heidegger’s links to Emil Lask (cf. Kisiel 1995), or indeed to Cassirer (cf. Rastier 2018); Carnap’s links to Cohen are almost completely neglected (cf. Damböck 2017), and the critical theorists, Adorno first among them, had of course only disdain for their old “masters”.
The same trend is to be observed beyond the bounds of philosophy: in
anthropology, the links of Lévi-Strauss with Cassirer’s philosophy of forms, in
linguistics, the Neo-Kantian undertones of the Prague and Copenhagen School, and
in sociology the many ties of Neo-Kantian social thought with thinkers such as
Max Weber, have generally been overlooked — or at least never considered
globally, as the symptoms of the general historical role played by Neo-Kantian
philosophy. This absence of Neo-Kantianism in the inter-disciplinary networks of
European science is revealed perhaps most clearly in the excellent, large-scale
reconstruction of the history of the human sciences in the late 19th and early
20th centuries offered by John Goldsmith and Bernard Laks in Battle in the Mind Fields (2019), whose only obvious lacuna is its
almost complete exclusion of Neo-Kantianism and its systematic, multilateral
ties with other mainstream traditions such as Brentanian and Gestalt psychology,
phenomenology, structural linguistics, or logical positivism. In a similar way,
Neo-Kantianism is conspicuously absent of most of the canonical work in the
theory of cultural transfers (Espagne & Werner 1998; Espagne 1999; Werner
& Zimmermann 2002) ) and has never been explicitly treated, by contrast for
example with phenomenology (Spiegelberg 1960) or structuralism (Albrecht 2007),
as an international movement. Classic studies of Neo-Kantianism (Köhnke 1986,
Beiser 2014) are usually obsessed rather with the logic of its development in
19th century Germany, or with the analysis of its
leading figures (Cohen, Natorp, Cassirer). The slowly increasing number of
studies that do take a decidedly intercultural and interdisciplinary
perspective, on the other hand (Dmitrieva 2007, Plotnikov 2005, Grifceva &
Dmitrieva 2010, Loft 2021), have brought up an extremely dense and interesting
network of exchanges and plausible channels of influences, interferences and
receptions.
This triple diagnosis of a) a (predominantly) monolithical focus on Neo-Kantianism as a German academic institution and b) a neglect of its systematic ties with other disciplines, and c) the presence of significant and undisputable examples of precisely such ties, in particular with Russia (Belyj, Pasternak) and Poland (Warsaw School of the History of Ideas) formed the basis of our resulting hypothesis, namely that Neo-Kantianism had to be studied not only as a philosophical method, but as a network.
To implement and test this hypothesis, we decided to proceed along two separate
avenues: the organisation of a conference with international experts of
Neo-Kantianism, whom we enticed to take a network perspective on the movement on
the one hand; the development of a digital project, th century European history of ideas, but that the
work has only begun in assessing exactly how it was so. Additionally, we
discovered that we are still lacking the proper methodological instruments, not
only on a digital level, but on a heuristic one as well, to frame and
interrogate the networks of Neo-Kantianism, a problem that Michał Mrugalski
addresses in his prospective contribution to the volume.
In summary, the present volume can be characterised both as a significant, mature
result in its own right, the formulation and confirmation of the systemic,
networked dimension of Neo-Kantianism and its heretofore neglect in the
canonical historiography of 20th Century European thought.
At the same time, it appears also only as a tentative and preliminary attempt to
characterise that systemic dimension, providing snippets and pieces of evidence
of bilateral exchanges, as a step to an unifying theory, or a synoptical
map.